Search This Blog

Monday, October 18, 2010

It is unlikely content has anything to do with existence

Does Content Have Anything to do with Existence?

Out of whatever it is that could exist, what is the relationship between content (what it is that would exist) and the likelihood of it existing? Two motivations for considerating this question are its intrinsic interest and how it casts the possibility of an explanation for existence.

If something is inconsistent the probability of its existing is 0. (Bill Vallichela)

What is the likelihood of something that is consistent existing?

I mention four cases 1. the actual universe, 2. possibilities 3. the sentences of a mathematical structure 4. quantum possibilia

1. the actual universe

We want an explanation not only for the existence of something, but for the specific universe we inhabit. In this case one would have to argue that our universe is that unique entity that could not not exist.

It is logically inconsistent that the universe not exist. But that would seem to be contingent and not a priori true.

The dualist would say I am giving too much weight to logic.

2. possibilities

What is the likelihood of the existence of a pink elephant outside my door right now? Given sufficient other information about the actual universe, there is a 0 probability. But why couldn’t there be a universe in which there things are pretty much the same but there is a pink elephant standing outside “my door”. (I put “my door” in quotes because I don’t know if it refers to the same ontological entity or not: there are two doors, one in each universe).

It has been speculated that all consistent things exist (see e.g. Tegmark()). This would at least give the answer to our question that consistency is necessary and sufficient for existence. This may or may not be true, but it leaves open the question of why something should exist just because it is consistent.

3. sentences

What if mathematical structure ontologically exists? Such structure is codified by the sentences of a formal system.

Might a sentence exist relative to itself? For the self-referential case we have

(1)  This sentence exists.

(2)  This sentence does not exist.

To the extent (1) is true (2) is false, but they exist equally. So the truth of a sentence does not seem to affect its existence. Therefore, it would be hard to argue that the content of a sentence makes any difference to its existence. As a result they all have equal likelihood of existing.

This would seem to rule out one kind of explanation for existence. The explanation involves the following. The universe is ultimately just mathematical structure. In fact, the universe just is the maximal theory T which implies that it necessarily exists. (Then, if we knew our universe to be such theory T, the necessary existence of our universe would a physical fact, and we would have an explanation for existence.) Without going in to it further, the problem is already apparent. Existential statements in T are irrelevant to the existence of T, as witnessed by (1) and (2).

What if sentences are not self-referential? I don’t know.

4. Conclusion

It doesn’t look good for an explanation for existence. On the other hand, I don’t know of a proof there is no explanation for existence (for some reasonable general class of notions of proof).

Friday, October 15, 2010

Content does not seem to matter to existence

(1)  The existence of this sentence is logically inevitable.

Is so relative to itself in the context of its (necessarily) possible definition...

But isn’t the definition contingent?

What we require is that in every possible world it is possible that (1) exists. But it is probably better not to use possible-worlds semantics at all. Then, (it would have to be argued) this possibility might have an ontological status indistinguishable from actual “self-apparent” existence. […]

So why wouldn’t every self-referential sentence exist? Compare (1) to

(2)  This sentence does not exist.

To the extent (1) is true, (2) is false, but they exist equally. So the truth of the sentence does not seem to affect its existence. Therefore, it would be hard to argue that content makes any difference to a sentence’s existence.

Nuts.

Can you see any way around it?

Thursday, October 14, 2010

Can the content of the theory be made relevant to its existence?

Can the content of the theory be made relevant to its existence?

If  so, we could have a hierarchy of theories based on how likely they are to exist. Such a hierarchy might be based on something like the following. Starting with the least likely to exist, consider T such that

(1) T ¢  Ø$T

I don’t know, hopefully there is no such T. If there were (and it was consistent) it would render the notion of existence within a theory irrelevant to the notion of actual existence. If there is no such T the notion of existence from within a theory is possible.

(2) T ¢  ($x)(x=x)

This T is the default degree of existence, because so many theories have this property. I don’t know if this is still valid when T is self-referential:

(3) T ¢  $T

This T would be still more likely to exist.

(4) T ¢  ƒ $T

This T would arguably be the most likely of all these theories to “exist”.

--Are there conditions stronger than (4)?

We want to rule out theories for which (2), but rule in theories for with (4). This is because we want to rule out the idea that all consistent mathematical structures exist. This would not be an explanation as to why any of them exist. Given that they all have the same existential status, why is it not the case that none of them exist?

One clue as to a way to proceed is that we want the why of its existence to be inextricably involved with its form (content). What does T have in (4) that it does not have in (2)? One thing is self-reference, but many sentences are self-referential. The salient property is condition (4), namely T stands in relation to the logical inevitability of its existence. Why should that matter? Because T’s existence is a necessary possibility.

(I have to remind myself: the reason we want condition (4) in the first place is that if we knew our universe was theory T, then it’s existence would be logically inevitable. The necessary existence of the universe would be a physical fact.)

What is a necessary possibility? Well, what is a possibility? Well, what does it mean to say such-and-such could be the case? In what ways does a possibility exist?

It seems plausible to say that a possibility exists the same way a number exists. Both of these are descriptions of reality.

Anyway, the first thing we do away with is possible-worlds semantics. Suppose we say í$T. It is not true that $T in some worlds and Ø$T in some disjoint set of worlds. What is true “in all possible worlds” is í$T. (Recall it is possible because we make no assumptions, so we do not assume nothingness is more natural than the existence of something.) Apparently

(5)  í$T  ®  ƒí$T

I don’t know if this respects the true-in-a-world and true-of-a-world distinction.

Then, the argument proceeds, the existence of the possibility of T is sufficient, in view of its peculiar definition, for it to bootstrap itself in to a valid notion of existence.

Tuesday, October 12, 2010

Reese

The Structure of Possibility

William L. Reese
SUNY of Albany

"For all we know logical possibility is the sufficient condition of ontological possibility."


"…The natural response is to say that in between it had remained an ontological possibility which lacked the conditions necessary for its actualization. Heisenberg made exactly that response to the question where an electron is between orbits. It retreats, he suggested, into possibility, and reactualizes in a different orbit."

Monday, October 11, 2010

Morato

Vittorio Morato

Other conceptions of sentences might be available according to which such
entities are necessarily abstract entities, that exist independently on the exis-
tence of their utterances and this because they exist already once a primitive
vocabulary and syntactic rules for a language are given. This position, however,
does not, by itself, exclude counter-examples like those presented above in the
case the primitive vocabulary or the formation rules are, in turn, contingently
existing entities or ontologically dependent on contingently existing entities8.
If we reason in strict analogy with what happens in the formal semantics for
modal logics, however, the basic elements of a language may be taken as al-
ready given \before" the various possible worlds enter the play; the existence
of a language (and hence of sentences) could then be seen as some sort of a
\transcendental condition" of the logic and therefore as independent on any
contingency represented by what is going on within worlds.

Towards a Materialist Explanation for Existence

It may be the title of this blog should be Towards a Materialist Explanation for Existence, but they don't let you change it.

Thursday, October 7, 2010

Focusing the Arguments

In light of Jesse's critique I sharpened a few requirements for T.

The first question is how do we justify the existence of T? The second question is why is it unique in existing?

The strategy for justifying the existence of T is: a reinterpretation of possibility, and a notion of relational existence.

We do not use the possible-worlds semantics for possibility. A possibility’s is ontology is not given by “possible” worlds semantics. In what ways does a possibility exist? It might be the case that the existential status of a possibility has some third truth-value u instead of t or f. This might be made plausible with an example form quantum mechanics. It is not the case that either x-spin is up or else x-spin is down for some electron in a superposition. We know this because Y-spin up is possible. So the existence of the possibility of y-spin up is not reducible to the worlds in which the x-spin is up and the worlds in which the x-spin is down. This way the possibility of the existence of T is not reducible to those worlds in which it exists together with those worlds in which it does not exist (recall we wanted to avoid the latter).

The second move is to say some things exist in a relative way. The number two exists relative to the number three. T exists relative to its own logical inevitability.

The second question is why would just T exist and not every possible thing? We want to argue that T is the theory most likely to exist out of all mathematical theories.

Brian Tenneson suggests that what exists is the maximal structure P (more later...).

Wednesday, October 6, 2010

Inevitable Existence by Jesse Folsom

The search for a unified theory of everything is hardly a new idea. None have succeeded in formulating such a theory as yet, at least one for which there is any sort of consensus agreement, and even if they did, at least one problem would remain unanswered. Such a theory might explain why everything is as it is, but it would still leave unanswered why there is anything at all. From a materialist perspective, it would seem that nothing existing would be far simpler and more sensible than all the complexities and interactions involved with something existing. Yet, the universe obviously exists.

What if the greater likelihood of nothing were illusory? What if the existence of something was not only more likely, but inevitable? Paul Merriam is attempting to formulate a theory which implies its own necessary existence without reference to any conditional statement. It's inevitability must, therefore, be totally self sufficient, proved without doubt within the statement itself, in the context of very bare predicate logic.

The difficulties of formulating such a theory are daunting enough in themselves, but the creation of such a theory is insufficient. Merriam must then attempt to correlate the structure of the theory to the physical universe. If this can be accomplished, a strong argument can be made that the theory is representative of the universe as a whole, but Merriam plans to go beyond even this. His claim is that the universe is actually pure mathematical structure, and that the theory is not just a representation of the universe, but is the universe itself. This is all towards the goal of a materialist explanation of existence.

Thus, an outline of his argument is:

  1. There exists a theory T, such that T's existence is shown to be logically inevitable within the structure of T.
  2. Some version of T, which we will label Tn, has a structure which reflects the structure of the universe itself.The universe is actually a set of mathematical relationships; it is pure structure, with all appearances of substance arising from this structure.The structure of Tn, being identical to that of the universe, not only represents the universe, but, because of the universe's nature, is the universe itself.Since the existence of T is logically inevitable, the universe itself, being T, is logically inevitable.





This idea is tempting, but is riddled with implied difficulties and even impossibilities. The existence of any such theory as T, which by implication necessitates its own existence in an unconditional fashion, is doubtful. It is easy enough to make a theory which states its own necessary existence, but there is no way to verify it. The basic structure of such a theory would be:

              T: Theory T necessarily exists.

Given that it contains no reference to any outside structure, there is simply no way to verify it. Its veracity is therefore indeterminate; it is not even worthy of being called “wrong”. This is why the theory cannot simply state its own logical inevitability; it must imply it through more verifiable assertions.

Merriam argues that since, according to part 3 of his argument above, all existence is relational anyway, T could exist relationally without any more “absolute” existence. Indeed, he goes so far as to say that it could exist in relation to itself. So long as it is possible that it exists, its relationship to itself could allow it to “bootstrap” itself into existence. Leaving aside whether it is even possible that such a thing exists, this would imply that anything which could possibly exist, does exist, since they would exist in relationship to itself.

An imperfect example is an imagined pink elephant towering over an imagined blue mouse. These two entities have a relationship to each other, he claims. Things must exist to relate to other things. But, of course, what exists in this case is actually a mental process, not an actual pink elephant and blue mouse. The pink elephant and blue mouse do not actually exist. This, in itself, should do away with the idea of purely relational existence, but in truth, the status of T, in this sense, is even worse. It is not relating to another object, even an imaginary object, just itself. Merriam says it exists “in relation to itself”, a circular and rather meaningless concept, and would mean that anything conceivable exists, which is clearly not true.

This brings us to a related difficulty. A theory is by its nature a mental object, residing within one or more consciousnesses. People formulate theories to represent some aspect of reality. But in order for this theory to accomplish its stated goal, showing the inevitability of the universe itself, the theory must not merely represent the universe. It must be the universe. Even if true, this implies that the universe is a mental object, and must have a consciousness to reside in. Given that the universe, apparently, predated any embodied consciousnesses, this places the materialist ends of this formulation in peril.






Another problem is that, even if the structure of the universe is purely relational, this leaves one big question: What does the universe relate to? If everything only exists in terms of relationships to other objects, what does the totality relate to to motivate its own existence? Saying it exists in relation to itself is meaningless, and further sounds rather akin to absolute existence. And what is the universe except the sum of its constituents?

Another problem is that a theory is static. A theory, once changed, is a different theory. Therefore, any theory of the universe cannot really be about how the universe is in all its detail, but only its regularities, those aspects which are unchanging. The differences within the universe from moment to moment, much less across eons of time, prove that the structure within those regularities is highly variable. Thus, this still leaves the question open as to why things are as they are. Why do humans exist, for instance. Modern experiments seem to show that even the quantity of matter in the universe can change, so this is not a regularity. So even if this theory were found, the question would remain why anything but a series of regularities would exist. Perhaps because regularities are only meaningful because they regulate the behavior of something? Even with this possible explanation, the deep logical quandaries of such a theory begin to be revealed.

Another issue, which Merriam freely acknowledges, is that a universe of pure structure disregards such phenomena as qualia. Such features, which are ineffable by nature, cannot be expressed in any symbolic language. As such, they could not be expressed in the symbolic language of the theory, nor even truly addressed within it. Yet even time is qualia-like in this respect, and a theory of the universe that doesn't explain time is a poor theory indeed.

What really dooms this theory, however, is how inconceivable it is to even get it off the ground. While Merriam denies this, while it is relatively trivial to write a theory that implies its own existence, implying necessary existence is an altogether different matter. Establishing necessary existence in the first place is likely impossible. If one could establish the logically inevitable existence of anything, one could then prove the necessary existence of at least some universe, such that the thing would exist.











Well, you could, except for an even deeper problem with this formulation, which involves the nature of logic itself. Merriam and many other modern scientists and mathematicians seem to think that logic and mathematics exist somehow independent of the universe, almost as if they were some sorts of Platonic ideals. But the truth of the matter is that logic arises as an epiphenomenon of the definitions we give symbolic language. That this cannot be not this arises from the definition of the word “this”. In other words, trying to claim some sort of truth-value to logic outside of semantics results in a circular argument. The logical properties of “this” are inherent to the definition of “this”. It is just a word, a collection of sounds with an arbitrarily assigned meaning. The symbols of formal logic are not words, but their meaning is arbitrarily assigned, nonetheless. If logic arises from language, then how can it be used to construct any universe, much less a logically inevitable one, in the absence of such symbolic thinking?